From Image to Icon: Art as My Encounter with the World
Daniel Raymond Chadwick
In progress
For it is said to be altogether impossible to suppose
that an artist should exist, since neither do we see anyone existing at the
same time naturally and from birth as an artist, nor does anyone turn into an
artist from being an amateur. For, indeed, one rule and one apprehension can either
make the amateur an artist or not at all.
But if, rather, one apprehension makes the amateur an artist it stands
to say, first, that art is not a system of apprehensions; for the person who
knows nothing at all would be termed an artist if only they were taught one
rule of art. And, second, should anyone
assert that, as soon as a person who has acquired some rules of art and still
needs one more, and because of this is an amateur, acquires also that one rule, and at once becomes an artist instead of an amateur by means of one
apprehension, and so will be speaking at random.
Sextus
Empiricus, The Outlines of Pyrrhonism,
3.29
1.
Art as encounter with the world is the dialogue between the artist and
the world, wherein the medium is artwork conveying the idea as Art through the
visual expressive journey by an icon that cannot be re-presented in words.
"Is Art more than interior decoration?"
In
my fourth grade, the school art teacher Gary Vanderbrook chose my artwork to
represent my elementary school class in a children’s show at the Albright-Knox
Art Gallery. My mother drove myself, a
neighborhood housewife, and one of my friends to see the exhibit. As we walked up the stairs to the second floor,
looming before us was a Jackson Pollock painting.
My
mother exclaimed disbelief that such a painting was on display, my friend said that his
little sister could finger-paint something more interesting.
I
didn’t know what to say. All I could
think was here was someone who thought about Art differently than I do.
2.
Art is a dialogue.
Art
is the medium in the dialogue between the artist and the audience whether the
latter consists of one person or many.
Analogously, as “eat” is to “life” and “death” so is “dialogue” to “Art” and “person.”
Thus,
Art mediates the dialogue between artist and audience through the artwork. This statement presumes that there are at
least two persons in the world, (1) the artist and (2) at least one person as
audience.
[Here,
“world” is everything or “the universe” and not restricted to the planet
Earth.]
I
take the position that there is more than one person in the world. I should say that I operate on this premise;
at the least, I operate as if the world consists of more persons than me.
[“Why
use the qualifier ‘as if’? State what is
the case directly.”
I
state definitions as I understand the terms but I qualify the situation since I
would rather be honest that I do not know the world fully. I am not a theologian who must provide non-falsifiable
answers to the faithful without empirical evidence and, at times, must do so
non-rationally (though not irrationally).
Additionally, I am not a
philosopher albeit I recognize the procedure of Sextus; i.e., the approach is
zetetic or seeking, ephektic or suspending judgement, and aporetic or accepting
a situation as a puzzle.
I
want to avoid pontificating on ambiguous subjects and practice humility. By contrast, asserting dogmatically what must
be the case contrary to appearances is the practice of ideologues. “…the stiff and unbending is the disciple of
death.”]
A
person is an entity who can think in rational and emotional ways (intellectual),
is able to understand that there is a past and a future as well as a present (temporal),
and is a subject who is concerned with the individual interest within a community
of other persons (intersubjectivity). A
person is a mind.
“What
if you are the only person who exists?”
If
so, then my reality consists of myself and my impressions, and then I think
there is a dialogue since it appears there are other persons with whom to have
it.
I
cannot prove that there are other persons outside myself, but I believe there
are so since everything corresponds to that reality as I perceive it.
Additionally,
dialogue may occur between my previous and current states; viz., in dialogue
one becomes both subject and object subject whether with others or
alone.
Whether
it is external or internal may not matter, in any case. It is not so much a matter of solipsism that
turns upon the solitary aspect of experience; instead, one accepts the
egocentric predicament as the limits of personal experience.
If
it is internal, then the appearances are my reality; if it is external, then appearances
are still my reality. The difference is
that in the case of the latter they do exist outside my mind and are not solely
a product of my mind. Whether I can know
for certain that these appearances exist in a world outside myself is doubtful
but, then again, I cannot be sure that these appearances do not exist in a world outside myself
especially since I have nothing as yet to compare or to contrast my current
state.
Only
dreams differ from this conscious state, though I have had dreams in which I
dream, and so I am left without an ultimate standard by which to make the
distinction possible.
Am
I fooling myself by creating Art for an audience only existing in an internal
reality? I think I am fooling myself no
more than if I decided to do nothing and decided that inaction was a way to
break into an outside reality. That
might be the biggest joke of them all.
Despite
the laughter—or because of it?--“One must imagine Sisyphus happy.”
Joking
aside, an individual recognizes or believes that s/he is a part of the
community of human beings, a species as an organic whole sharing cultural
artifacts. I am not physically separated
from other human beings as I sprouted from other human beings, apparently. This is the beginning of intersubjectivity,
the sharing of origins between two subjects who are in dialogue.
[A
cultural artifact is that transmission of knowledge or skill or outlook by
various sciences and arts that people in a society share (E.g., math equations,
manners, folk wisdom, images, preconceptions, great events, bad habits, technical
know-how, popular tunes, urban legends, and even clichés).]
I
should note that as far as we can perceive, human beings sprouted from this
planet and we came out of it along with many other diverse kinds of
entities. So this leaves the possibility
that there may be an intersubjectivity, a sort of dialogue, however weak,
between human beings and other entities, whether organic or mineral. Perhaps even between human beings and others
beyond this planet since all came forth from the heavy elements of stars, and
then perhaps some day to return to them in another state.
Meantime,
the human dialogue developed over many millennia and achieved results that to
the first human beings would have been in-credible, literally so. That I can see today is the result of such
magnificent achievements.
Thus,
I believe that there is a dialogue among human beings. In particular, the dialogue between the visual
artist and other persons takes place through the visual medium of the
artist. For the visual artist it is the
visual Art.
Art
is a medium facilitating dialogue between the mind of the artist and the mind
of the audience. As such, “Art” means particular artwork that
presents ideas that are relevant to the medium; in this case, visual art
presents visual effects. “Art” also
denotes the visual artwork that does more than offer visual effects but also
psychological effects. Further, it may
provide another way to consider reality.
“Artwork”
is the particular or peculiar piece of visual art that provides the medium for
Art between the artist and the audience.
Practically, the artwork is the transmission of visual effects and
philosophical idea of the Art. The two,
Art and artwork, may be not always the same given either the artist or the
audience.
The
conversation that takes place is not one-sided as not only is there the medium
of Art but there is also the interpretation of the viewer.
Of
course, the artist is responsible for creating Art since that is the
medium. It may be better to say that the
artist is responsible for producing Art.
Why so?
The
artist did not create any of the
materials involved in the production of an artwork. S/he did, however, employ materials to
produce Art. Having said that, I may state
that the artist “creates” a work as it is that which did not exist previous to
the production. Even if it is a copy of
another artwork it is that which did not exist before its production.
If the
artist has produced something then it began in the mind of the artist, which
mind is not only a biological product but also one of shared cultural artifacts. To interpret, one looks to these shared
cultural artifacts.
Without
the interpretation there cannot be knowledge.
“I
know the facts so that means I know.”
This
person thinks that Fact = Knowledge.
This
is wrong since a person may know many facts but is unable to put them together,
relate them, in a cohesive way.
“Chadwick
weighs 155 lbs, this is a fact.”
Still,
one must relate “Chadwick” to “155 lbs.” through the verb “weighs.” Also, one need understand a meaningful
association between “155” and “lbs.” The
speaker takes it for granted that the sentence has an immediate interpretation
according to a conventional set of understanding of the relations. Nonetheless, s/he gains that understanding
only after struggling with this in learning the language through mediate steps
of understandings and hearing such idioms repeated times.
If
I write “Chadwick weighs 4.3 pood,” using the old Russian weight system, the
sentence has less meaning to the English speaker.
A
person may perceive a brute fact but then needs to interpret it in order to
gain knowledge. Fact ≠ Knowledge but Fact
+ Interpretation = Knowledge.
This
does not mean that knowledge, in itself, is necessarily derivative of this
process since there may be knowledge of
things (i.e., aware that they exist), whereas this is knowledge about things and consists of an
understanding.
“Overstanding”
may be a presumption; “sidestanding,” an association.
Interpreting
artwork is unlike interpreting some other entities that are falsifiable since
Art allows the audience to offer multiple understandings of which many may be
legitimate. All one has to do is to
review essays concerning any artwork.
Granted, there may well be a special point an author had in mind, but
there likely were many special points and one interpretation may not grasp them
all in any moment.
Also,
an artist may not be upset if artwork yields an approach which s/he did not
consider when creating Art. The artwork
may transmit another perspective through the interpretation. Of course, a particular comprehension may fit
many artworks.
Viz.,
as a philosopher might say, one noema may have many noeses whereas many noemata
may yield one noesis. The artist agrees
inasmuch that Art is not the result of either the philosophical search, the
scientific method, or of religious development in that only “questioning” or “one
answer” or “one process” will suffice, although it has something in common with
all: the wonder of curiosity. E.g.,
Art
|
Philosophy
|
Religion
|
Science
|
Reflecting values, subjectively and objectively,
but also consists of…
|
Questioning values
|
Affirming or Rejecting values
|
Testing, or Experiment with, values
|
[It is intriguing that sometimes a person’s interpretation reflects the person more than that which they interpret. This is the mirror paradox of interpretation. E.g., this statement of interpretation (either subjective or objective genitive, a statement resulting from interpretation or a statement about interpretation) “It is intriguing etc.” probably reflects me as much as it is an observation about how people tend to interpret. (Is the phenomenological reduction possible?)]
The
emphasis on the artist’s intention so as to gain one particular interpretation
mistakes artwork as a mathematical formula; i.e., the mistake is the presumption
that the artwork yields only one end.
Nonetheless,
the emphasis on the interpretation as the beginning point for multiple
intentions mistakes artwork as a utility of reflexion; i.e., the mistake is the
presumption that the artwork is only a means to as many interpretative ends as
there are interpreters.
In
daily dialogue people may take much of this for granted. Use of idioms are shared cultural artifacts
that one does not notice either as an end or as a means to an end until (1) one
is misused or (2) one new to the audience presents itself.
Likewise,
artwork may offer shared cultural artifacts that people take for granted either
as an end or as a means to an end until (1) one appears to misuse the usual
image or (2) a new image presents itself to the audience.
Here,
image = appearance.
“Appearance”
might be the same as representation in visual art, but it is not the same as
re-presentation since the teleology differs.
Teleology,
the aim or purpose, should not be confused with intersubjectivity or the
dialogue between persons but may result in dialogue.
This
complicates the dialogue between the artwork and the audience so that it may
require open and free discussion that it might help to sort out the effect.
“No
one is able to dialogue freely since each person is conditioned by habit or
construed so by nature to approach each event in a particular way.”
What
one is by nature is, apparently determined; e.g., a human being cannot fly,
cannot breathe underwater, etc. Can a
human being decide to act in alternative ways, however?
“No,
a human being cannot decide to act but in the pre-determined alternatives by
personal constitution which s/he decides as to how to act.”
The
spontaneity of events may cause reactions that differ from one’s usual
deliberation.
“The
event and inveterate habit determined the reaction.”
Can
a person act against personal inclination?
Let
v = value distinctions and let n = the number of choices.
v = n (n – 1)/2
So with two choices there is only one value
distinction to make, but with three choices there are three. Not too bad, but with five choices there are
ten value distinctions one must make. Et
cetera.
As the number of choices increases, the number of
distinctions one has to make multiply even more, and so one wonders if the
increase of choices is a freer or more restrictive state.
[Does anyone really think this way? Reviewing a menu and its many choices, how
many people take into account n
amount of entrees and then weigh the v
among them? Though if they do not does
this mean that their choices are determined?]
Determinism
may be the case, but even if so,
1. I
still cannot predict the future with perfect accuracy,
2. I
am still surprised by events, and
3.
I still may find pleasure in life.
Thus,
a dialogue between the audience and Art or a dialogue about Art may well be
determined but still be
1. unpredictable,
2. surprising, and
3. pleasant.
The best one can say is that dialogue takes place
that appears to be free.
The
dialogue between the artist and the world also includes those entities that are
not, as far as is known, able to perceive the artwork or do not have what one
considers “mind” in the full sense as the previous definition of “person.”
Artwork
includes various aspects of the world; e.g., a star, sadness, a Guinea Pig, intellectual
arguments, gaiety, a bolt of lightning, psychological states, and a chunk of
quartz. Thus, the artist brings these
aspects into the dialogue and tries to understand their places in the world.
[Thus,
if there are no minds in the future, could the dialogue take place between the
artwork and the world in the relation of the two?]
While
one may ask how the artist understood the aspects of the world, the “one” needs
to be a mind asking that question. If
there are no minds, then are there questions or even a dialogue?
At
best, one may say that behind the artwork is the mind of the artist in dialogue
with the world, this is the encounter of a presence seeking union with that
world in a moment. Indeed, the artwork
is a record of that dialogue, the re-presentation of that presence.
In
that sense, one may say that the artwork is a fossil of a previous dialogue
awaiting discovery by other minds.
3.
Art is an expression.
More
precisely,
Art
is a non-rational expression.
Visual
art is a non-rational visual expression.
An
“expression” is an expression of
something; i.e., it has content.
[I
do not mean that it must consist of an image that corresponds to an external
appearance since it may be an appearance of the internal. The internal appearance is the dark
luminosity of the content. “Dark” in
that no one else can see it, “luminosity” in that it is the brightness of the
idea. “Content” may consist of either the
psychological extension or the projection of reality in the re-presentation of
an idea.]
The
image is more important than the content as it both offers the appearance (artwork)
and conveys the content (Art).
E.g.,
someone feeds a mathematical equation into a computer drawing program, or
another draws a re-presentation of an understanding of Quantum Mechanics, both
erudite motivators, to be sure. Still,
one asks, “Is the drawing any good?”
Someone
says, “I want to paint a landscape image in order to re-present both the scene and my idea about it”
or
they say
“I
want to draw an image that extends my
psychological state into it”
or they
say
“I
want to sculpt an image in order to project
another reality.”
When
one re-presents an image by extension or by projection then the image is an
icon. Without one of these, it is mere
representation of appearance rather than the re-presentation of the idea of the
appearance.
To
clarify, a re-presentation is not an imitation in another dimension; e.g., abstracting
three-dimensional space or even four or more-dimensional space to
two-dimensional imagery. Instead, a
re-presentation presents again the appearance along with the idea, the idea as
either an extension or a projection.
[An
idea, more formally an Idea, offers the extension or the projection of the
artist’s thoughts as the re-presentation of an appearance.]
The
artist searches for a way to make the idea concrete; viz., s/he figures out how
to express the idea visually. The
questions include:
1. What medium?
2. What form?
3. What shape?
4. What color?
5. What texture?
6. What technique?
[“Form”
and “shape” may not be identical terms if one employs three-dimensional
objects. “Shape” may note the
two-dimensional look from one perspective while “form” may offer whether the
intrinsic nature of the object is, for instance, organic or mechanical. “Texture” may apply to two-dimensional
re-presentations as well as three-dimensional ones.]
Each
of these statements is rational and involves a rational process; the processes,
such as automatic writing, may be random which seem irrational or the imagery
may appear irrational.
[Some
have remarked that “automatic writing” in the hands of visual artists is a
cheat since they edit that image; i.e., they do not simply allow it to stand on
its own. Viz., the rational shapes the
irrational process.]
Artists
use rational means to express the non-rational, a procedure appearing to some
as irrational.
“Irrational”
might mean that an artist discovered how a non-rational instrument achieved a
rational expression. E.g., Apelles,
frustrated by his inability to paint the foam of a horse’s mouth, chucked his
sponge at the painting in anger and noticed that it gave the impression he
desired.
But
it also may indicate the processes those as Max Ernst utilized, whether
collage, frottage, decalcomania, etc.
Visual
art is about the visual.
An
artist is not overly concerned with how it is visual; viz., s/he may have an
interest as to how one perceives through sight other objects and whether this
perception is the result of the relation of the subject to external matter and
its primary or secondary qualities that offer sense data that impress the
idea-in-the-mind…
…or
whether it is that primary and secondary qualities are the same and so of
relating to sense data that stimulate the idea-in-the-mind…
…or
whether it is a “bundle of perceptions” and the visual experience of ephemeral
phenomena…
…or
whether it is the sense percepts of a
priori concepts of Space and Time…
…or
whether it is suspending judgement and reducing the appearance to an essence…
…or,
finally, whether it is the biological reaction to light stimuli.
Nonetheless,
visual art is not an aspect of either Philosophy or Science though it may
contain aspects of each of these.
[Certainly,
a philosopher or a scientist may discuss a philosophical or scientific aspect
of Art from the trained perspective and do so fully. This does not mean that Art is either
Philosophy or Science since that confuses these categories as equivalent. One does not say that the class of philosophical
commentaries on Art is the same as the class of Art re-presenting philosophical
commentaries, it is not a commutative identity.]
Visual
art is an aspect of matter insofar as it is material, and,
it
is an aspect of energy inasmuch as it is a result of energy.
This
is the case of any production, whether by human agency or by others.
Is
any product of human effort the same as Art?
Any
product is a re-presentation of a human idea.
Is it an extension of the psychological?
“I
constructed this desk with some new wood and some old pieces according to my
deliberate plan.” This is a re-presentation,
but not an extension, which does not mean the desk is deficient in some way but
it does mean it is not Art.
Can
furniture be Art? Yes.
“I
constructed this desk with some new wood and some old pieces according to my
deliberate plan so as to extend my feeling about a person’s place in the
interior environment.”
This
is Art. Could it go further?
“I
constructed this desk with some new wood and some old pieces according to my
deliberate plan so as to extend my feeling about a person’s place in the
interior environment and to project another kind of reality.”
If time
is an aspect of matter and energy,
then,
the matter and energy in a created work presents a time dimension—
however
construed astronomically, existentially, or scientifically.
How
does visual art accommodate these venues?
Visual
art in astronomical time is mundane reality as mere recognition of a world-in-movement
whereas visual art in existential time is the psychological reality as alert to
one’s commitment to the world as well as the artwork as a record.
Visual
art in scientific time of either quantum mechanics or relativism is previously unknown
by personal experience, at least to me.
As
an aside, there have been, and are, many people who believe they have
encountered a multi-dimensional or time-less situation.
Keep
in mind that belief and knowing are not the same.
Someone
says “I believe there is a drawing in front of me.”
Another
person says “I believe there is an angel in front of me.”
Is
the first person more likely to be correct?
S/he may imagine, hallucinate, or be mentally jeopardized. This does not mean the second person is
stating the case but it does mean one is more likely to believe that the first
person knows something that is the case.
[Who
dies for what they know? And yet, how many people were, and are,
willing to die for what they believe?]
A
person may believe anything without induction, deduction, or abduction, but that
same person cannot know anything without reliable means.
If
believing were the same as knowing, I would have fewer but more solid
beliefs. If knowing were the same as
believing, then I would be a more ignorant man.
[People
kill others and nations go to war because of either political or religious beliefs.
People rarely kill others and nations, as far as I know, have never gone
to war because of knowledge.]
“An
artist operates by intuition.”
Intuition
is immediate knowledge about one’s sense; it leads to a belief about that which
is outside the self. Most define it as
immediate knowledge of the external world, but it is inward knowledge that leads to belief about the outer world.
Foundational
reality = Metaphysics, which only means a view of reality and is not
foundationalist since that view may change.
Which
is true:
“Visual
art is a representation of the world”
or
“Visual
art is an extension of the world” or
“Visual
art projects the world.”
Each
of these statements indicates how one thinks about visual art, about the vision
of visual art;
viz.,
it indicates either one’s comprehension of visual art or the possibility of
visual art or it does both. It is no longer a matter of whether a
2-dimensional image is abstract or realistic or in-between. Instead:
Representation
= mundanity.
Extension
= psychology.
Projection
= metaphysics.
Representation,
Extension, and Projection indicate a reality of a space.
Nonetheless,
there is no indicated space in reality but displacement of entities.
Displacing
entities is no small matter but is a re-ordering of the world.
A
juror accepts the last work, sculpture α, into an art show which means there is
no room for sculpture β which was among those the judge was considering for the
last spot. The art show now consists of
a number of art pieces, n, which
includes sculpture α.
“Why
is this sculpture in the show?”
“The
juror accepted it.”
One
may imagine any number of combinations of art pieces on display with other
judges who are in control of the acceptance or rejection.
Likewise,
one creates that which has not existed before and re-combines material in a new
way, displacing the entities of material with one entity.
How
is the creation of Art different from human production of any object?
This
representation of the physical space is the mundane aspect of Art in the world;
i.e., its physical reality but as a vehicle for an idea is a re-presentation.
The
artist creating Art reveals the many distinctions of the query “why.”
“Why”
splits into several kinds of questions about cause-and-effect concerning Art,
certainly as much as other human activities.
“Why
did she feed her child?” appears to be a simple question that one may
distinguish as
Love,
affection for her child,
Care
for a helpless human being,
and
a Need to attend to others.
There
are still other reasons such as
Transferring
superfluous food to a hungry person,
An
obedient response to a command to feed the child,
and
keeping the species alive.
How
to construct appropriate categories is a matter of the mundane, the
psychological, and the metaphysical, and one applies these to Art.
“Why
did she draw the picture?” is usually of the psychological distinction; i.e.,
what motivated the artist in terms of emotional feeling. A mundane distinction is that drawing
materials were available to a person who has that skill. The metaphysical distinction involves the
artist’s intellectual conception of reality.
The
Art of Dreams,
Dependents,
Deviants,
Drug
Addicts,
and
the Depressed
provide
a way to forms previously unknown and not experienced.
One
may ask: does one need to be in a state
of dreaming, dependency, deviancy, drug addiction, and depression to express
representation, extension, or projection?
No,
for I say that
the
Art of Alertness,
Independence,
Steadiness,
Health,
and
Happiness
also
provide a way to forms previously unknown and not experienced.
E.g.,
both Depression and Happiness are revelatory
states that may be alien to the usual human routine.
All
these forms share the non-rational expression of Art, an expression that can be
a bridge among human beings.
As
a bridge among human beings, Art expresses the presumed communication of an
experience that takes place among human beings.
The person takes care to apprehend the mind behind the artwork so as to
convey that perception to others. Thus,
the bridge is the sharing of interpretation of Art that takes place between two
minds.
Interpretations
may divide but they also engender intellectual participation about the human
vision. Interpretation may be an
activity of conflict but it also may be an activity of critical construction in
the way engineers design a project. The
blueprint is drawn up after discussion wherein the discussion was a bridge
leading to the blueprint.
The
expression of visual art yields the human vision of the world, whether a vision
of the reality of that world (re-presentation),
another
vision of the reality of that world (extension),
or
a vision of the reality of another world (projection).
4.
Visual art presents a vision of a reality.
This
is not just in the sense of “visionary” (i.e., extension and psychology) or in
the sense of “literally” (i.e., representation and mundanity) but also in the
sense of another world (i.e., metaphysics).
Art
re-presents either another vision of reality or a vision of another reality.
Visual
art effects the visual perception but cannot effect the personal
interpretation.
“I
am suspicious of people who smile in subway cars.”
Appearances
do not deceive, presuppositions do.
Socrates
was mistaken or, at least, Plato was mistaken, in asserting that the painterly
icon is less true. Since Plato put this
in the mouth of Socrates in The Republic,
I will refer to Socrates.
After
questioning Glaucon, he determined three levels of the table:
1. The table is a Form or Idea.
2. The table the carpenter builds is one s/he
abstracted from the Form.
3. The table the painter draws is one s/he
abstracted from the carpenter’s table.
Hence,
the painterly depiction is less true as it is twice removed from the Idea.
The
mistake Socrates made was that he understood the image as an imitation of a
table.
[Of
course, the image is not an imitation of a table but it is an image of a table,
“Ceci n’est pas une pipe.”
An
imitation of a table might be another
table the carpenter builds. What the
carpenter builds, however, is part of the process of giving shape to an idea;
it is neither a corruption nor a distancing of it.]
Artwork or craftwork, at the least, is a re-presentation of an idea rather than imitation. As
such, it is no longer an image but is an icon, a reality in itself.
The break with the Platonic approach is this: artwork is not an imitation of an idea but the re-
presentation either by psychological extension or metaphysical projection and a culmination
of the artistic idea as an icon.
It is not a matter of seeing the shadow of the Form but it is the reality of the Form incarnate.
The artist’s idea is incomplete as image until the artwork is complete as icon.
Most people prefer the imagery of decoration since
Art is overwhelming. Nonetheless, for
those who can endure it, display of content in a new image of an icon may lead
to the wonder of curiosity.
An
artist creates according to an understanding of the world; a decorator creates
according to style within its own environment.
Art
tends to the intuitive, a connection to mysticism and immediate knowledge,
although there is no necessary implication of a supernatural world. This is Art as subject.
What
about scientific knowledge? Scientific
knowledge goes beyond “knowledge of” artwork.
One “knows of” an artwork in the individual sensorium, even an infant
“knows of” the various noemata, the things perceived.
The
scientific approach allows one to understand phenomena as to its material
existence; i.e., to know about it. In the process, one knows the dimensions,
structure, and chemical composition of an artwork. More popularly, one may also try to set the
artwork in an historical situation or in a cultural context as sign
(indication) or symbol (metonymy or metaphor).
In
any case, whatever the direction of the scientific approach, the person
comprehends the artwork as object.
The
following table is a chess game,
Karl Marx vs. Meyer, 1867
|
|||
1 p – k4
|
p – k4
|
15 b x b
|
q x b
|
2 p – kb4
|
p x p
|
16 n x kbp
|
n – k4
|
3 b –
qb4
|
p – kn4
|
17 q – k4
|
p – q3
|
4 n – kb3
|
p – kn3
|
18 p – kr4
|
q – n5
|
5 o – o
|
p x n
|
19 b x p
|
r – kb1
|
6 q x p
|
q – kb3
|
20 b – r5
|
q – n2
|
7 p – k5
|
q x p
|
21 p – q4
|
(k4)n – qb3
|
8 p – q3
|
b – kr3
|
22 p – b3
|
p – qr4
|
9 n – qb3
|
n – k2
|
23 n – k6+
|
b x n
|
10 b – q2
|
(q)n – qb3
|
24 r x r
|
q x r
|
11 (q)r – k1
|
q – kb4
|
25 q x b
|
r – r3
|
12 n – q4
|
k – q1
|
26 r – kb1
|
q – n2
|
13 b – qb3
|
r – kn1
|
27 b – n4
|
n – qn1
|
14 b – b6
|
b – n4
|
28 r – b7
|
resigns
|
…where
“is” or the verb “to be” neither asserts a relation, nor denotes a property,
nor is implication, nor is existential, nor is identity, but is class-inclusion;
i.e., the table is one in the class of chess games. I.e., it is a chess game of many played.
The
table is a re-presentation of it and a chess player sees it as more than an
object. Is it an image?
There
is a presence behind the game, and there are two: Marx and Meyer. How are these presences known?
One
problem is that the table consists of numbers and letters. Artists use numbers and letters to make
images, however. Further, I have used
this table in a drawing as part of an image, The Grand Calculator.
Nonetheless,
the table on its own is a literary schedule of moves more than it is a visual
re-presentation of an idea. Here,
context provides a clue.
One
knows not only of the game from the table, one knows about the game. The table is an object re-presenting the game
as a schedule.
Writing
“This is the 1867 chess game between
Marx and Meyer” then “is” is a mark of identity. If you play out the moves, then you are playing the 1867 game between Marx
and Meyer.
A
diagram of each move of the game on the board, here showing the end result,
might be an image (or if all moves display, then a series of images),
…but
is it an icon?
The
re-presentation of the appearance of the chessboard, just as the previous table
of moves, has two presences behind it; i.e., Marx and Meyer. Insofar as it is a visual re-presentation and not just a literary one, I might concede
that this is, indeed, an image more than a diagram.
Inasmuch this does not convey the extension of the projection of the artist, it is
not an icon. At best, it is an image
that decorators might employ for a design as well as a diagram that chess
enthusiasts might use for study.
Again,
as with the table, one knows not only of the game from the image, one knows
about the game. As an image of
decoration it may be a subject for dialogue, as a diagram of study it is an
object re-presenting the final appearance of the game.
What
about the intuitive approach? The
intuitive approach allows one to enter into dialogue with the artwork. Art, as a dialogue between audience and
artwork, is the recognition of a presence behind that artwork.
That
presence is the subject, the artist, the individual who is a person who
comprehends the world in terms of intellectual, temporal, and intersubjective
relations. The viewer may know
scientifically about the artwork as object, but s/he also knows the person who
created the artwork. The person in dialogue
with artwork apprehends the artwork as the presence of a subject.
[As
Jean Luc Godard mentioned in an interview, “SMS” as “send message” really means
“Save My Soul.” He thought that both
the sender and the receiver wish to be in dialogue so as not to be alone; thus,
receiving the text is not just a reading of words but an apprehending of a presence behind those words.]
Scientific
knowledge about the artwork lends to comprehension of it as object in terms of
its physical characteristics as well as its historical and cultural
contexts. This knowledge may help one
understand the artwork so as to aid in apprehending it as subject.
Scientific
knowledge is comprehension of an object; mystical knowledge is apprehension of
a presence. Artistic knowledge is the
sober intoxication of realizing the apprehension.
“The
art was a symphony of color, a mystical apprehension,” as one may read in various
descriptions, but it still is primarily visual apprehension. The mystical, the intuitive, the immediate
knowledge of the senses—this is how one grasps Art.
[An
apprehending of a presence is more than just a “knowledge of” or even more than
“knowledge about” a presence.]
I
cannot prove that there is a presence behind Art. And yet, by abduction one infers reasonably
“If an image, then an artist.” What
about images created by other species or by machines? Then the presence is either that of a
creature of another species or the abstracted human presence in a machine.
The
non-falsifiability of Art is notorious though it plays positively unlike the
role it plays in Religion.
“I
like this drawing.”
“This
drawing displeases me.”
“I
like this religion.”
“This
religion displeases me.”
The
lack of disproof has caused and may cause quarrels among artists and Art
schools but it does not lead to large-scale armed conflict.
Religions
cannot make this claim.
Nonetheless,
the conflicts may cause new ideas to develop and change the Religion or the
Art.
There
may be many people who find Art uninspiring, but no one disbelieves it.
Religions
cannot make this claim.
The
questions, however, may cause Artists and the devoted to re-consider their
positions.
A
view of reality that one takes for granted is more difficult to pin down than
is commonly thought.
The
foundationalist claims that there is a solid standard of understanding; the
relativist claims that there is a shifting standard.
The
foundationalist states that all human dwellings from the first up to the
present have entries. No one tries to walk through solid walls unless
s/he either is a comedian (slapstick) or is mentally jeopardized (physically or
psychologically).
Nonetheless,
it is possible that human beings can pass through solid surfaces but do not
know that they can do so. This is
similar to the predicament of the gnat or fly, the insect which tries to get
through an open window pane but cannot perceive that it only has to go around
it.
The
possibilities of quantum tunneling by a human being may occur, nonetheless, “We
operate as if we cannot walk through walls.”
How
many would take the effort and time to discover whether this might be the case? I think that the number would be much less
than those who would expend time and effort to earn enough to buy food.
If
there are human dwellings that lack an entry then they are not typical
structures but may be intended for another purpose rather than what one
comprehends about residential dwellings or housing.
Has
there ever been a society in which people constructed housing without entries?
In
any case, here is the crux of the matter; the foundation is the operating
function as to how human beings think about the external world and not the
external world itself. The relativism is
the approach to that view of reality.
The pragmatic effort, the “cash value,” is often made for what appears
to be the case and less so for what does not—what is the network of belief and
knowledge causing an individual to hold what makes sense?
Foundationalism
is another name for how a person functions, Relativism is a name for the degree
of variation in the shifting understanding as to how a person functions. Pragmatism here is the name for whether a
person bothers to act one way rather than another way according to the
perception of reality.
The
artist may offer a personal view that is foundational to the internal world but
relative to the external world. S/he invests her time and effort into that
picture of reality.
The
internal world is the psychological; the external world is the reality or the
metaphysical.
As
previously stated,
the
psychological is the extension
and
the
metaphysical is the projection.
Applying
the idea to concrete visual appearances is the struggle of the transition for
the artist.
For
instance, a person wants to re-present the extension through a particular
projection but a cultural artifact may shape the idea. A cultural artifact may be a linear narrative
or an object of decoration or a conversation piece.
Hence,
even this picture of a reality is not always according to the personal
imposition. E.g., human beings may
structure a story about their life in the way nearly all books and cinema films
depict life; a visual artist may do this unwittingly. Nonetheless, that is a narrative one reads
into one’s life instead of the reality of the haphazard. The narrative becomes the procrustean bed as
one edits those annoying or tragic scenes.
This
is why Bunuel films as Un Chien Andalou
are one of the few films that make sense to me as real life rather than as a reel file.
5.
Explanations and arguments are not substitutes for experiencing an icon
of Art.
Art
may present a story but cannot be only a story; otherwise, it is illustration. Someone writes that “images produce a story”
but if that is all they do then the story takes precedence over visual art.
If
one can explain an image by words alone, then that image is a failure.
Explaining
Art explains the punch line, words weaken the image.
Additionally,
conflicting explanations of Art lack the force of arguments in other fields,
especially when the artwork yields multiple interpretations because of its
obscurity or yields little understanding because the artwork is idiosyncratic.
[Idiosyncrasy
is a difficulty for any artwork and perhaps more so since the 20th
century than in any previous era. The
lack of a universal belief system, save nationalism (which itself is a fairly
recent invention of philosophical fiction that assembles several groups of
varied backgrounds under the rule of national law), the decline of religious
membership, and the new ideals in history of either political or economic
philosophy (whether by John Locke or Emerich de Vattel or Adam Smith or Karl
Marx et al.), the rise of psychology, the success of scientific models to
re-present the world accurately, all pose obstacles to those who wish to unite these
old, new, and different streams of thought as well as religious, social, and
political movements into one, cohesive guide.
Without
an accepted set of values, without a myth (and by “myth” I only mean a
narrative by which one grasps meaning of the world), the artist is left to a
personal view that might be tough for a viewer to comprehend the image, much
less apprehend a presence in dialogue.
The
philosopher prophesied: “And now the mythless man remains eternally hungering
amid the past, and digs and grubs for roots, though he have to dig for them
even among the remotest antiquities. The
terrible historical need of our unsatisfied modern culture, the assembling
around one of countless other cultures, the consuming desire for knowledge—what
does all this point to, if not to the loss of myth, the loss of the mythical
home, the mythical maternal bosom?”
And
Nietzsche wrote this in 1872!]
I
do not know if either representational or non-representational Art or anything
in-between is more or less universal.
Re-presenting the idea is more than the ability either to draw a figure
or to mix colors. The adventitious
perception of either a recognizable shape or feeling a mood in non-representational
artwork has its advantages and disadvantages.
Likewise, noting either a direct connection with corresponding reality
or a shared mood in representational artwork has its strengths and
weaknesses. Even if both are universal,
the idiotes, the peculiarity, of much
artwork may obstruct the viewer’s understanding as much as its bizarre charm
may attract attention.
[The
attitude of many artists after the mid-20th century who believed
that representational artwork was inferior was intriguing. I do not question that non-representational
artwork opened up another route to imagery, I do not question those forms I
find inspiring. Their mistake, however,
was to maintain that this became the only route to imagery.]
Still,
despite obscurity or idiosyncrasy many people, whether highly educated or not,
deny the need for interpretation. I know
that interpretative explanation cannot replace the experience but as noted
previously it is necessary to enter into dialogue.
“I
have no interpretation” reveals the naivete of a person, whether a layperson
concerning theology or the scientist regarding philosophy. These individuals do not recognize that is
not so much a matter of the literal study either of sophos or of theos but
simply a matter of accepting the tools that one uses in order to understand
phenomena.
Students
ask me about conflicting perspectives of Philosophy or of Religion. E.g., a Christian student thinks the African
approach is best, another holds to the Catholic understanding, etc. What is the problem? The Bible contains enough ambiguity to make
all theologians happy.
The
problem with judging Religion is the same as judging Art.
“He
who keeps Israel
neither slumbers nor sleeps.”
“Go,
your sins are forgiven.”
“That
color is attractive.”
“This
color is disturbing.”
Lack
of standards of disproof for these statements does not mean they state the case.
Likewise,
Art contains enough ambiguity to make all viewers happy.
[Falsifiability
is an approach with which most people are unfamiliar, and it is the other side
of verification. Falsifiability is the
lack of disproof whereas verification is a proof. Scientists say that Science is not a matter
of proof (i.e., verification) but mathematics is a matter of proof. Science is a matter of the lack of disproof
(i.e., falsifiability). This is one of
the reasons why scientific models change but mathematical proofs, as far as I
know, do not.
Art
and Religion, however, are two topics that have neither verifiable nor
falsifiable characteristics by which to judge them. It is one thing for me to write about the
idea, the re-presentation, etc., it is another thing for me to state that one
artwork is superior or inferior to another.
Hence, the importance here to discuss as to how people may judge Art.]
The
agnostic in Art may accept all as Art but may not.
“I
do not know if this is Art but it may be so.”
“I
think this is not Art but I cannot prove it.”
There
are several kinds of agnostics: Metaphysical, Ethical, Epistemological, and
Logical.
The
metaphysical agnostic claims that
there is a dialogue that is unresolved.
E.g.,
Art offers extraordinary sensations…and…Art offers ordinary sensations. The reality is ambiguous, and ambiguity is
debatable; hence, unknown.
The
ethical agnostic cites the Epicurean
trilemma about divinity; viz., is the divinity benevolent and impotent or malevolent
and potent or is the divinity a benevolent and potent being that allows cruelty
in the world? Relevant to Art, --one
asks if the artwork is skillfully presented but not imaginative or unskillfully
presented and imaginative or skilled and imaginative but cannot re-present the
artistic idea.
The
epistemological agnostic would appear
to be a redundant category since agnosticism is, by definition, about
knowledge. And yet, the epistemological
agnostic concern is only about the intellectual problem of knowing without
relation to reality or to ethics or to logic.
Still one can split epistemological agnostic into at least two
approaches.
Using
the religious example:
1. One believes that there is a supernatural
world but it is unknown, or,
2. one believes that no one can disprove the
idea and it is a mere matter of falsifiability.
By
analogy with application to Art,
1. one believes that there is a re-presentation
that is an extension or a projection but it is unknown, or,
2. one believes that no one can disprove that
there is either an extension or a projection; viz., artistic ideas, as
religious ones, turn on the point of lack of falsifiability.
The
logical agnostic states carefully
that sensible statements that are also logical are either tautologous (“A
single person is an unmarried person”) or a
priori (“He is six feet tall and so is less than seven feet tall”) propositions.
So
one reads the following from the Gita or from the Dao:
“There was never a time when I did not exist,
nor you, nor any of these kings. Nor is
there any future in which we shall cease to be.”
“Man
follows the earth, Earth follows heaven, Heaven follows the Dao.”
Likewise,
in circles discussing Art one reads,
“The
superior artist is the one whose work encompasses significant past art
movements.”
“It
is impossible for an 'advanced' artist to bother making a portrait.”
“This
black shape imposes itself on the tan background as the fated doom at the door
of life.”
These
are all propositions that lack tautology and are also not a priori statements.
Since
one cannot know Art logically either by tautologous or by a priori propositions, then it becomes a problem of constructing
meaningful statements about Art.
[A.
J. Ayer commented that this meant that such statements lacking the tautologous
or a priori qualities were
non-sense. Alonzo Church replied that
this could not be the case, since there needs to be an ultimate principle upon
which there is a sense or a meaning, at least insofar as human knowledge is
concerned. I may not be able to “prove”
logically why a drawing is Art, but that only means that I can go no further,
logically, in order to do so.
For
my purpose here, it is sufficient to remark that the qualitative and
non-falsifiable natures of artistic statements and statements about Art
necessarily differ from quantitative and falsifiable ones and cannot be judged
by those standards. A possible improvement
upon this position is to take an agnostic position about such statements and
classify them as non-logical or non-rational rather than to say they were
non-sense. I.e., the “sense” may be
neither logical nor rational.]
The
one who rejects Art as a necessary human endeavor is also a problem. There are several kinds who reject Art:
Cultural, Religious, Materialist, and Philosophical.
The
cultural rejection consists of
negating Art as necessary to human life or alien to human society or
superfluous to economy.
In
religion, one sees this in history in the Hellenistic era (c. 300 BC – AD 300)
and the thinkers of the time describing the Second Temple Jewish community as
αθεοι, “atheists,” since said community rejected other gods.
Today,
the society that lends importance either to the political ideology or to
religious fanaticism or to the accumulation of capital to the exclusion of all
else, perceives the pursuit of creative ideas as either
1. superfluous to the aim of the State (hence, useless), or, against the State (hence,
dangerous), or,
2. as sinful obstacles to the aim of the
religion, or,
3. as an endeavor that is only useful as a
commodity (a means) but not as a good-in-itself (an end).
[Those affirming the last point transform themselves
into decorators to confirm the status quo for the sake of profit. Profit is not bad at all but it is not the
aim of Art. Profit is not the aim of a
prophet. Those who say otherwise have either misunderstood or are ignorant
about Art or have little soul or are mean-spirited; further, they are one step
away from kitsch.]
The
religious rejection is the question
about the aim of Art; the belief that Art is an obstacle to the ideal rather
than instrumental. I.e., Art is vanity
and deflects attention from the religious ideal.
The
religious judge asks: who judges Art?
Similarly
so with the question about a non-falsifiable enterprise as Religion; i.e., who
judges Religion?
[This
yields two ironic statements:
“The
greatest threat to any Christian church is Jesus.”
“The
greatest threat to any Artwork is an Artist.”]
The
materialist rejection is that Art is
insignificant as a mental good. Instead,
it is only a material good. E.g., for
the capitalist, Art is either a commodity or only a means of marketing as property; for
the communist, it is either impractical or only a means of propaganda.
The
philosophical rejection is that
individual expression is best suited to a higher form of contemplation rather
than realizing higher forms in actual visibility for the contemplation by other
minds. Art is not an intrinsic good but
an image only that may be a means to
the greater good.
I
do not think that it is a matter of “viewing Art in a certain way implies
viewing Art in a certain way,” a principle of identity wherein “p implies p,”
but I think it is more a matter of inclusion than identity. I.e., p may imply p, true, but for the
artist p may imply not-p since else p would not have an identity unique to itself
as opposed to, say, q or r. In sum,
there would be no need to identify p if there were neither q nor r.
Numbers
furnish an example here. “1 implies 1”
but I understand it better as compared to -1, 0, or 2. A mathematical square here illustrates this:
This
9 x 9 matrix offers multiple perspectives of “0”; i.e., whether one goes
through horizontal rows, vertical columns, or the two diagonal crosses,
addition of the numbers always adds up to zero. Either nothing is understood unless against something or nothing implies the lack
of something.
One
may find oneself caught up in the experience of Art when discussing it, the
discussion led to that re-presentation of the Art in the imagination. Hence, p, the discussion as either
experience, or as agnostic, or as rejection, implied not-p, the Art.
The
principle of inclusion: It is the case that anything implies something else
besides itself.
Hence,
a person may view Art in more than one way but any of the ways imply, and must
give way, to the experience.
6.
The image in the mind, the image applied, the image explained; these are
three aspirations to Art but they are not the icon.
Here,
the sums of the aspects of Art are not equal to the whole. As an experience, however, the part may be
the epitome of the whole. The whole is
no greater than some of its parts.
“The
whole is no greater than some of its parts.”
This
works with infinity—the series of even numbers or of odd numbers is no less than
the series of all numbers—but why not also daily events?
Consider
the Aldersgate Street
meeting experience of John Wesley, upon hearing a reading of Luther’s preface
to Paul’s Epistle to the Romans, in which Wesley wrote that his heart was
“strangely warmed.”
The
series of abstraction follow:
Ancient
Israelites to
Hellenistic
Judaism to
Various
branches to
Jewish
followers of Jesus to
Paul
of Tarsus to
Writing
a letter to Roman Christians to
Luther
reading it to
Writing
a commentary about Romans to
Writing
a preface to the commentary to
A
reading of the preface to
Wesley’s
hearing of the reading to
His
experience of his heart “strangely warmed.”
Any
one part in this chain may cause an experience. Concretely for Methodists, however, Wesley’s
experience is the culminating epitome of the preceding 1700 year history of
life and literature as the origin of Methodist Christianity. This part of the series is equal to the whole
for Methodists.
Likewise,
consider the chain of events that leads to an Art experience:
An
artist experiences an idea in the mind to
Refining
the idea to
Reckoning
how to put the idea into visual terms to
Applying
the idea to
Sorting
out the means of application to
Collecting
materials needed for application to
Executing
the application to
Editing
and revising the artwork to
Exhibiting
the artwork to
Someone
writing an explanation about the artwork to
Someone
reading the explanation to
The
personal experience of understanding the artwork.
Again,
each one of these could be the experience for a person, although some may
obstruct the full experience and this includes the artist as well as the
audience.
E.g.,
applying the idea of the mind to an image may be limited by technical means as
the artist may be unable to re-present the idea as faithfully as s/he would
like to do because of lack of proper instruments or of proper skill and
training.
One
may state, “Do not be constrained by technique but be moved by the image.”
“Fine
words, but fine words butter no parsnips.”
The
artist who wants to produce a lithograph but does not have the instruments at
hand is constrained by technique regardless of creative movement. Still, the aspiration to create and the lack
of the usual instruments may cause the artist to employ, or even realize, a
process previously ignored.
I
do not want to know my artistic limits, I want to discover them.
Applying the image and discovering artistic limits:
does this mean producing tens or hundreds of re-presentations in the hope that
one gains the right image?
One may as well begin typing words at random in the
typewriter, not even as a stream-of-consciousness but picking out words by lottery.
Any artist may take risks of a visual challenge but
s/he may not be a poor-odds gambler.
Does applying the image mean that the artist produces
tens or hundreds of fine variations of the same re-presentation as in an
assembly line?
The artist is not a machine.
An artist is both a mystic and a scientist, but also
is solely neither.
The
artist creates art, Art changes the world.
Imagination and creativity come first, technique and
process next, dimensions and application last.
The imagination and creativity of some people are
higher than those who are artists.
[To understand this, consider that some persons who
present qualities one may attribute to a specific group just as some of that
group do not present those qualities.
Granted, one thinks that “it is not the case that one
is an artist and is not an artist.” This
is the principle of non-contradiction, that “it is not the case that x is p and
not-p.”
And yet, in this sense, a couple paradoxes as dialetheisms
present themselves:
“Some of the best Christians (Buddhists, Muslims,
etc.) I have known are not Christians (Buddhists, Muslims, etc.).”]
“Some of the best Artists I have known are not
Artists.” This statement is unacceptable
to many for logical reasons.
[Naturally, it is convenient to distinguish between
what is the case and what is not. Also,
for our mundane observations it appears that the law of non-contradiction helps
human beings to operate reasonably to survive.
For instance, a pedestrian about to cross the road
sees a car motoring in the lane s/he is about to cross. I believe that the pedestrian is better off presuming
that it is the case that the car will occupy that space and not another when
s/he is about to cross it.]
Nonetheless, more severe situations and different
environments may require another way to consider the actions under
observation. In the wake of the advent
of both Quantum Mechanics and Relativity, physicists see the world in another
way that is unknown to many, perhaps most, people. Husserl was right, and I think remains
correct, that these sciences and their powerful conceptions are still not a
part of everyday experience and it would be tough to get at the essence of such
an experience. Even if one could
experience such events first-hand is it possible for that person to put this
into intelligible language? “To be or
not to be” is not just a cry for sanity but also a question about reality.
[Of course, Husserl was also correct to imply that
these remain a part of our world; hence, we cannot separate ourselves from them.]
A drawing presents this better, perhaps, than my
fiddling with logical propositions:
This drawing is not just one object but offers at
least four possible objects simultaneously:
1. A small
cube in front of a large cube.
2. A large
cube with a section cut out from its corner.
3. A small
cube inside a corner.
4. A flat
shape of geometric figures.
The duck-rabbit illustration is a famous example of
this problem. Similar is a drawing of
Teiresias:
One may see not only the face of a man with a beard
but also a naked woman.
This brings us to the manner as an artist would
understand it.
The
principle of ambiguity: It is the case that one is p and not-p.
I cannot offer proof that this ambiguous state of
humanity, the Teiresias paradox, may be the ground of creativity, though I
think it is reasonable that it is one of the conditions that cause human beings
to understand the world through other perspectives. The artist remembers, however, as in the case
of Teiresias, that the gift of the seer may lead to the tragedy of blindness.
The human imagination appears to be one of the
catalysts of Philosophy, Science, and Religion just as it is one of the
catalysts of artwork.
The achievement of each of these endeavors is richly
diverse, attesting to the power of human imagination in the aspiration to an
ideal. Likewise, Art presents multiple
forms of expression.
Here, I understand that imagination leads one to a
concept.
One imagines a re-presentation that leads to a
concept and, when applied either as an extension or as a projection, conceives
it as applied to artwork.
The human mind may
conceive only that which the human mind can
imagine.
If this is the case, then it would be contrary for
the human mind to conceive what is beyond its imaginative power. I can
barely imagine my past experience and conceive all that I perceived at those
times; how much less can I imagine that which I have never experienced or that
which is unimaginable.
I cannot conceive the unimaginable by definition.
This does not mean that whatever a person imagines
must not exist beyond the mind;
neither does it mean that whatever a person imagines must exist. It does mean,
however, that it is unknown.
It only means that it may be because of this tension
between the two possibilities that an artist desires to bring the artwork into
existence in order to resolve the ambiguity.
Abstracting the elements of visual phenomenon in
artwork and relating those elements is the duty of interpretation.
Therefore, what the human mind can imagine the human
mind may conceive is also that which the human mind can interpret since the
visual phenomenon is not beyond its imaginative power.
Applying this to human visual creation, I would
organize it into three groups based upon the sense of sight, the capability of
the intellect, and the feeling of the non-rational (emotional) aspect of a
person. Can there be more kinds than
these? Of course, but for the sake of
illustration as to what constitutes a one-to-one correspondence to sight, mind,
and feeling, three is practical. So, at
the risk of building a scheme that may say more about me than it does about
Art, I present the following points.
There is a main class of human visual creation that
has at least three sub-classes in which one finds the three kinds of visual
production: the decoration, the image, and the icon.
The decoration appeals to the eye.
The image appeals to the eye and to the mind.
The icon appeals to the eye and to the mind and to
the heart.
As noted previously, the artwork that provides the
skillful use of shape or color at the least is some kind of image. An image that attracts the eye without
relating to the intellect remains decoration without attempting to be Art. This is not “bad” but it does make one ask
whether decoration is not as good as some artwork. I think that this does happen when one may
see in the swirl or the flourish the values of a civilization. Here, I present as evidence productions such
as Anglo-Saxon or Celtic illumination, Persian carpet design, Islamic
calligraphy, and even Oriental writing.
Likewise, an image that appeals to both eye and mind
is certainly artwork though it may not go as far as the icon. The problem here is that this is an even more
subjective topic than the other two as the elements under discussion are
non-falsifiable. E.g., are
wall-paintings in houses, whether from Antiquity or the Mannerist period or
even those of Goya, artwork which aspires to something more than decoration? Certainly, in the case of Goya, I think
so. In other instances, and it appears
more so for the work in Antiquity, it does not.
On the other hand, I think that the paintings of pre-historic societies
on the walls of caves aspire to be iconic as they relate to all three; at
least, I think they do.
So one must remember the problem of relative values,
so well noted by Sextus millennia ago, and that the decoration may well be an
icon as may be the image, and then I have to go back and re-order the points as
to what is “decoration,” “imagery,” and “icon.”
The problem, and more to the point of this section,
is whether the image in the mind, the image applied, and the image explained
are aspiration to, or equivalent with, the icon. Of course, one may substitute “decoration”
for “image” but I prefer to stick with the term “image” as, at least, an
“appearance.” “Image” here is the
non-reducible term.
Once an artist thinks of the icon as a process or as a concatenation of caused events, then one has lost the vision of the idea as an organic growth or even as a picaresque journey with all its possibilities offailing and struggling to overcome obstacles in the creative purgatory that aspires to heaven completion while careful of the hell of failure. Besides, there may never be a final cause in the eyes of the interpreter.
Once an artist thinks of the icon as a process or as a concatenation of caused events, then one has lost the vision of the idea as an organic growth or even as a picaresque journey with all its possibilities of
7.
The Artist takes a journey that is both an extension and a projection
through the re-presentation.
Many
who wish to be Artists travel the trodden paths of previous and other Artists
or, worse, they only read about it but do not engage Art.
One
sees this happening among the devoted religious as well as the scholars who
study the story through various commentaries, anecdotes, and legends. Many engage the mythology, but the lucky few
live out the myth.
In
the same manner, among Artists many engage Art “in the style of” other Artists
and want to see the world as these Artists saw it (as if that could be done). Re-presenting the presence of another artist
is inauthentic. Many engage the style,
but the lucky few live as an artist. How
does one begin this journey but by a genuine scrutinizing and questioning of
one’s own view of Art?
[To
reassure the reader and ask for patience, I am using the principles of seeking,
suspending, and accepting the situation as a puzzle. The constant questioning about what may have
been thought certain has likely been irritating but this kind of engagement is
necessary in order to avoid falling back on habit and convention. Habit and convention are convenient in
mundane matters but may cause blindness toward the unusual or the unique. I think an understanding of Art requires at
least this concession. Re-presenting
the presence does not mean that one will encounter it unless one scrutinizes
and questions. E.g., in reading about
Alexander the Great one meets the person of Alexander. What happens when one discovers that the
earliest existing work about Alexander was written by Diodorus nearly three
centuries after his death? Should this
lessen the reader’s experience? No it
should not, because, at least, one experienced the writer’s presence, if not
also that of Alexander.]
The
question may be that which no one can answer and few might know to ask; is the greatest
Art that which no one can produce and that few would wish to see? This is the first step. Taking this step, the artist breaks from
others who work from habit as s/he tries to bridge to the idea rather than cater
to social convention, drawing the world through personal reflection.
I
want to create images that one cannot classify so easily or shelve into
categories.
Next, having taken the responsibility to produce such artwork that may not be possible, and even if possible that no one will wish to see, the artist makes the journey from idea to icon.
Throughout
this journey, the image is the re-presentation of forms whether abstracted from
nature or from one’s aesthetic sense.
How the artist employs these forms so as to touch upon the mind as well
as the heart is the next obstacle of this venue. To arrive at the completed artwork, to get at
the final form, the Art, the artist may need to extend the mind and project the
personal perception, exercises that one may not take to so naturally. Many people may have empathy with Art, but
this does not mean that many people can produce artwork. And even if so, it is not necessarily the
case that one will communicate well to others even if they wish to see the
artwork.
Overcoming
this obstacle, there are still the unknown detours that present themselves, the
unaccountable—serendipitous?--associations of related interests that the artist
sees as the image develops. A shape or a
color or a figure may remind the artist of another related entity or even a
style that, as enthralling as it might be at the time, was never a part of the
idea. I do not know if many artists
struggle with this as much as they should do, and especially so if they have an
idea.
Understandably,
the artist’s idiom is restricted to the personal history which is within the
larger historical context. Although if
the artist loses sight of the idea for which s/he is attempting to re-present,
then there is the danger of falling back onto forms and styles from the world
of the past. Forms and styles that made
sense in their previous temporal and social context may not fit so smoothly in
the present and the future. Concentrating
on the idea, yes, the cultural artifacts of the time move the artist who is
ever mindful of their relation to the past and to the future, avoiding
idiosyncrasy but translating them universally through the personal idiom of the
visual art.
I
offer these three alerts not to restrain artists but to remind them that there
are at least three diversions on the road that will lead them away from the
form of the idea into the final form, the icon.
The
icon may have the property of fecundity, extending the psychology and revealing
the metaphysics of the artist so as to yield more forms. The production of these forms may be a surprise
even to the artist though s/he plans a particular result through training and
experience along with the designed studies about the outcome. Part of the reason is that the idea may be
riddled with both the ideals and the flaws of the person, and, ironically, the
flaws make artwork accessible to others and prevent Art from becoming
idiosyncratic, allowing it to be universal. The idea itself is indifferent to these flaws
as the flaws help convey the universality of human understanding.
[Intrinsically,
human beings have flaws. Nonetheless,
these flaws are instrumental in conveying the idea into the artwork since they
shape the idea to some degree. The very
perspective of the idea is that of the flawed, human perspective, and likely
understood best by flawed human being.]
This
may be the absurdity of Art; the attempt to delineate the idea as ideal fails,
but the artist fails triumphantly in the completion. If I wish to understand life, then I must
accept its absurdity. If I want to
understand Art, then I should accept its logic of contraries, contradictions,
and inequalities. Naturally, this means
that, regardless of whether determinism is the case, a person cannot know the
future of Art.
Truly,
the future of Art, the future of all forms, is unknown and frightening, but it
is also surprising and full of hope.
As
the artist continues the journey to the future of all forms s/he will pass
through the conception of internal reality of the mind to the perception of the
external reality and offer up both in artwork.
[Although
I caution the reader about any notion concerning a mechanical process for
Art. One may begin with an external form
and then see the internal idea.
Understandably, one may also counter that the external form may just be
a prod to what is already in the mind but that is unknown. Remember that I am not writing a textbook as
to “how to do” Art but instead one that explores Art as an encounter with the
world.]
The
conception of the internal reality in the artwork is the extension of the
artist’s psychological state whereas the perception of external reality is the
projection of the artist’s metaphysical understanding. The extension is the appeal to what used to
be called the soul and the projection is the appeal to the mind. The artist unifies these by Art, and so offers
an icon.
[This
does not mean that the artist presents an answer or a tautology or a
discovery. The artist looking for a
method to make the beautiful will not find it but only through the struggle for
a visual re-presentation of the personal perspective. Religious discourse aims for “the answer.” Mathematical forms are tautologous; the sign,
=, means that one side must equal the other.
Scientific process, a mix of induction and deduction, may present change
as scientists realize that the outcome may not be compatible with their model. The change of the artist’s journey is both
instrumental and intrinsic to the thought of the artist. It is instrumental in that the artist may use
random technique and apply these to the artwork. It is intrinsic in that the artist plans but
is open to new developments along the way whether these are technical aspects
of the craft, psychological apprehensions, or metaphysical understanding. ]
The
icon is not the end of the journey since it offers the dialogue continuously to
other persons, past and future, as well as among other artworks, past and
future. Together, the icon and the
artist are on a journey that may be asymptotic; viz., always nearing the
destination but never reaching it as the dialogue splits into many possible and
fulfilling pathways. The encounter of my
artwork with others may lead to the dialogue of ordered ecstasy, that of one
presence apprehending another presenting at least one more perspective of
understanding.
8.
I do not like to write about Art, I want to experience it.
This
is the distinction: words do not substitute for the sensorium—the individual
theater of the world—but words are one way to clarify understanding and
interpretation of the sensorium.
As
synecdoche it may be the case that words substitute for all senses not as in an
example of onomatopoeia but as in “I read the book of the suburb/the forest/the
city/the swamp/etc. and understand the language that surrounds me.”
A
literary device, however, is not a substitute for the experience and it is an
added linguistic experience, an alien
intrusion, into the sensorium. This
threatens to remove one from the experience and replace it with its own
peculiar aspect of reality.
Even
employing prose and metonymy and allowing for specific descriptions, reading
the review of a play or of a concert is not the same as attending the play or
the concert. These words may dilute the
experience but they may also help one recollect various points of the
experience.
Can
the interpretation enhance the experience?
I think it can and I have experienced this myself. Nonetheless, there have been times when an
interpretation has steered me in the wrong direction and caused me to miss
another aspect of the art form. The problem
is what I noted previously as the mirror paradox of interpretation in that sometimes
a person’s interpretation reflects the person more than that which s/he
interprets.
Of
course, if art is an interpretation, then in this sense a work of art may be a
self-portrait.
This
is a metaphilosophical dictum that is not self-referring.
Although,
one may wish to think that this statement is an interpretation and a portrait
of me.
Interpretations
are stated re-presentations of Art and abstract the elements of artwork in both
communication and medium;
“one
does not read a loaf of bread, one eats it.”
One
“reads” a loaf of bread as not only bread but also as the staff of life, the
home, a mark of agricultural civilization, the center of a family meal, et
cetera. And one desires nourishment when
one is empty.
As
the devout person fasts so to make room for the ideal, the artist empties
oneself of presuppositions so as to make room for the idea.
If
one wishes to experience Art, then one needs to exercise the epoche, the suspension of judgement.
“…usefulness
comes from what is not there.”
While
it may be impossible to remove from the field of perception the intruding
figures of habitual (individual) and conventional (societal) attitudes to
artwork, at least one may recognize that these attitudes may hinder one’s full
and open perception. Realizing what is
obtrusive to clear perception and attempting to see without them is more useful
than trying to verify the habitual and conventional perceptions, the
“expectations.” Lacking these habitual
and conventional apparatuses may confuse a person since their omission has made
life more convenient to understand, but their employment has also taken for
granted phenomena. The sudden surprise
of seeing for the first time results
in the anguish of Roquentin who, upon realizing the gnarled, doughy forms of
the roots of the chestnut tree, must recognize the living reality of the tree. This is Roquentin’s crisis of perception, and
becoming nausea, as removing the comfortable and convenient notions of
philosophical essences and, perhaps, even what is known biologically about
trees, he encounters the tree as that which exists now in the present instead
of seeing it through the personal habits and societal conventions of pre-framed
attitudes.
This
“existential now” is the decisive moment when a subject, a person, experiences a turning-point, a crisis, of another entity and
rather than comprehending the other as an object in history, apprehends that
entity as immediate presence. This
moment has no temporal limit consciously as the person is unaware of the
passing of time. This is what the
mystics have called the stationary
movement.
I
think that the right perception of Art is this meditative moment that has a
contact with eternity not as a long time but as time-less.
For
instance:
A
person reads a book or watches a play? A
matter of hours.
A
person relates to another person? A
matter of a lifetime.
A
person views an icon? This is time-less.
Maybe
Heraclitus was correct; “Eternity is a child playing.”
The
limits of language about Art are not the limits of Art but merely the limits of
language.
In
an attempt to demonstrate the variation, some say that language is about denotation whereas visual art is about connotation. This may lead to a table prepared between the
two as one would construct a table to reveal the similarities and contrasts
between Anglo-American and Continental philosophies, to wit;
Comparisons and Contrasts between the Literary and
Visual Arts
|
|
Literary
|
Visual
|
Narrative
description of imagery
|
Iconic
|
Concerns
denotation
|
Concerns connotation
|
Individual detail
|
“Big picture”
|
Sign
|
Symbol
|
Which is
it?
|
What is
it?
|
Conception
|
Concept
|
Temporality of narrative
|
Time-less, “existential
now”
|
E.g.,
nouns, verbs, adjectives, adverbs, etc.
|
E.g., communication
|
E.g.,
color—“red, orange”
|
E.g., color—“hue,
intensity, value”
|
E.g.,
character—happy man, loving woman”
|
E.g., “humanity, emotion”
|
Of
course, reading presupposes a time element.
The poem, however, is not temporal intrinsically and is closer to the
“existential now” of the icon. Reading a
poem or viewing an icon, however, does involve a linear process of time but is
not the dominant temporal feature of the experience.
Nevertheless,
I think the approach of this chart is incorrect since it presumes to order
visual art by literary means. One may as
well order literary arts by visual means, and one way that is done is by
illustrations, graphs, charts, and tables.
When that is done it results in an image that is not iconic.
This
is a division similar to that of “mathematical art” noted previously. Most “math artists,” at least in the visual
arts, are trying to understand and conceive Art through mathematics. Formulae may become mass-produced banality.
The
artist, however, attempts to understand and conceive math through Art, and that
is the difference. The former is still the
mathematician, the latter is the artist.
Analogously,
one draws a comparison with the study of Religion and the religious
experience. A scholar of religion may
provide a list of the broad genres of religious literature as:
Myth
Legend
Folklore
Ritual Instruction
Records/Genealogies
Wise Sayings
S/he
might add poetry and prophecy, unless shelved under “Wise Sayings” or combined
with other genres. Regardless of the
categories and their organization, these, and the expert study of them, are not
the religious experience.
And
so it is similar to the problem of understanding Art as an experience, as the
way one encounters the world. Reading
and writing about Art, discussing the imagery of a particular artwork, each of
these may be cover a degree of the experience or even a corollary result, but
none of them are the entire experience of the encounter with Art.
I caution
against taking this as the principle of the excluded middle, however, that “It
is the case that it is either p or not-p.”
The reader sees this in the preface quotation of Sextus Empiricus, that "For either one lesson and one apprehension can make
an artist of the amateur or they cannot do so at all."
Sextus,
although questioning rightly the approach, proposed a false dichotomy by stating
that one lesson and one apprehension makes someone an artist when it may be a
matter of degrees of ability. Because of
this, he was also employing the word “artist” in a narrow way that presumes
that there is no variation.
Likewise,
each of these activities may be a variation of the experience of Art by degree,
and even by kind through activities not directly involved.
So
it may be for an artist that s/he sees this subtlety more so than others.
This
“something between” signifies a degree of both and one could argue that the
conjunction “or” is inclusive (all cases possible) instead of exclusive (only
one case possible).
[I recognize
that degrees between black and white should mean shades of gray between
them. I think that would be a good
illustration but I wish to point out an additional perspective to this
topic. Also, the differences between two
cells may be simply a matter of position of one or many other cells between the
pair whether they are black or white.
The number of such cells is as infinite as that of the values that are
between black and white and it will also reveal the importance of the variation. In the “logical law” one reads it as a linear
movement left to right, at least in the English language, and the linear aspect
tends to blur that there are other, possible tendencies. Further, the grades are not only horizontal
but also vertical; the direction in space may be as significant as the subtle
tint of color. ]
When
several rows of cells align together, this changes the view so that the
horizontal lines no longer appear parallel but on a slant:
For
instance, when one reads “artist” then one thinks of how that individual is an
artist whereas others are not or are not quite as so or maybe more so in a
particular area. “Artist” implies by
complementary association not only those who are not but also those who are
neither an artist nor entirely unskilled.
True, one may be an artist or not but there are many who are in-between
at various degrees.
[Complementary
association is that which one may “fill in the blank” where “blank” does not
mean “nothing” but a vacuum of meaning that one fills with a cultural
artifact.
Likewise,
hot/cold,
light/dark, soft/hard, love/hate, noise/silence, high/low, et cetera. Unless there were variations of a state of
heat or of light or of sexuality one could not distinguish any entity from the
Parminidean One. Hence, I can identify p
because of its particular characteristics and I know these are particular by
comparison with other entities; i.e., p implies both p and not-p.
Aristotle
employed these kinds of complementary and associative pairs to show a Golden
Mean or a balance between them for human beings and their rational action.
E.g.,
the Mean between foolhardiness and cowardice must be courage.
So
“courage” may imply both foolhardiness and cowardice and any degree of these behaviors. p implies both p and not-p.
The
associative complementary pairs are equivalent to a combination of relative and
absolute terms in propositional logic.
True,
p may imply not-p by its complementary association. Another aspect of
this,
however, are the grades between p and not-p.
What is additionally intriguing is that one may not figure on the
degrees of variations in the use of complementary pairs such as “man/woman”
whereas it is more easily understood for pairs as “sweet/bitter” or
“rough/smooth.”
Likely,
this is because one may figure on grades between relative terms as
“sharp/blunt” but may not expect them in terms thought to be absolute such as
“man.” Putting “man” into the pair of
“man/woman” may appear to lack degrees of variation to those born before the 21st
century in the West, but this absolute understanding of sexuality is fading as
a past cultural artifact. Humanity does
adapt to new situations, however. It is
granted that human beings can adapt to bad environments, but can they adapt to
good ones? (Is it so that the sharp distinctions about sexuality that those of
us learned in our upbringing in 20th century Western society were fairly
recent in history?) As a logician once wrote, all words have
relative meaning in any case as dependent upon their use.]
The
artist, amateur, and all those in-between may experience Art, as the union with
a presence in that moment of continuing dialogue of minds which transcends the
final union of the artist with the world, whether that final union is atomization
into a new cosmic order or is apotheosis into a new cosmic glory.
[One
day some men visited Abba Anthony. Among
them was Abba Joseph. Abba Anthony
wanted to test them with a scripture and, beginning with the youngest, asked
each of them what it meant. After each
replied, he said “You have not understood.”
Finally, he asked Abba Joseph who responded, “I do not know.” Then Abba Anthony proclaimed, “Indeed, Abba
Joseph has found the way, for he has said, ‘I do not know.’”]